28 Definition
Highlights of this Chapter: we give an axiomatic definition of the integral, and use these axioms to prove the fundamental theorem of calculus, as well as several corollaries such as
-substitution and integration by parts.
The integral is meant to measure the (net) area. When
Thus a good theory of area would immediately lead to a good theory of integration. But how does one measure area? Perhaps surprisingly, this turns out to be much more difficult than it sounds - and all the difficulties weren’t worked out until the beginning of the 20th century with the advent of measure theory.
We will not need the full power of this theory here - areas under the graphs of functions are a special enough case that we can develop a theory of integration independently. But our beginnings will be the same: area is a concept we struggle to define explicitly even though we know many rules it should behave. Thus, area is a prime target to try and characterize axiomatically, and then seek an explicit definition that realizes our axioms.
What are some natural axioms for area? Perhaps the most fundamental is that area is additive: if
It turns out this simple rule alone is enough to provide some axioms, which completely determine the theory of integration (for continuous functions, at least).
Remark 28.1. In fact, the definition of a measure is just a slight generalization of this: a measure
- For all
, - If
is a countable set of disjoint sets in then
A measure on
28.1 Properties of Area
We will try to produce some axioms for integration as a net area. Consider a function
For the integral of
Next, if
And, finally if
These rules do not seem like much, but we will see that they are quite powerful: they completely determine the behavior of the integral for continuous functions.
28.2 Axioms
To take an axiomatic treatment seriously, we need to first make these rules more precise. The integral we have described is a function: it takes an input (a function on an interval) and gives a unique output (a real number). But what is the domain? A first hopeful thought might be “all functions” - but we might want to be wary of imposing this from the outset. After all, we have seen that real analysis allows many monstrous functions (like the function which is 0 on the irrationals and 1 on the rationals) that we might not want to - or even be able to - assign an area to!
In fact, this worry is quite real: the Mathematician Guiseppe Vitali showed in 1905 that there are subsets of
Example 28.1 (
We now show that
Now, if
First, if
A similar argument prevents
It follows from this that certain subsets of the plane cannot be given an area: in particular, if
cannot be coherently assigned an area, and thus we cannot assign a value to the integral of
Remark 28.2. This construction of non-measurable sets is a fancier version of the following argument that there can be no uniform probability distribution on that natural numbers: (for instance, this is the kind of thing you implicitly assume exists when you ask someone to pick a random number)
Say you want to assign each integer the same probability
And if
Thus, because we’ve realized that trying to assign an area to all subsets of the plane (or even all regions under the graph of a function) is too much to ask, we need to specify as part of our theory a class of ‘integrable functions’, and impose our axioms only on those.
Definition 28.1 For any closed interval
If
then is an element of for any interval andIf
and for all thenIf
is an interval and , then if and only if and . Furthermore, in this case their values are related by
Note these axioms do not aim to uniquely specify an integral, but rather to delineate properties that anything worthy of being called an integral must have.
Example 28.2 (The “Constant Integral”) The first axiom tells us that if a constant is integrable, then we must have
So, let
- Axiom I, by definition
- Axiom II: if
and then so - Axiom III: Since for any
whatsoever we have . Using this for an arbitrary yields
Thus, the assignment
This integral is not particularly useful, as it is undefined for any non-constant function. One can make it slightly better by extending to an integral for linear functions
Exercise 28.1 (The “Linear Integral”) Let
Here we have spelled out the domain (of functions) clearly for the proposed integral, and given a formula by fiat. This is not the usual means of constructing an integral of course, as it requires we sort of already know the answer! The usual way we will let
28.2.1 Properties from the Axioms
In all of the following we assume that
Proposition 28.1 If
Proof. Let
Thus, we assume
By subdivision, we see that
Subtracting the common integral over
Proposition 28.2 If
Proof. Again this is just subdivision at work: for any
The above proposition has a short proof because it did not claim much: we learned nothing about the nature of the area function
Theorem 28.1 If
Proof. Let
But subdivision (Axiom III) implies
Thus
So, we choose
Thus
Remark 28.3. Of course, the proven result is not really stronger than what was asked, since we began on a closed interval, and we know that continuous on a closed interval implies uniformly continuous.
However, if you look carefully at the proof you see we nowhere used that the original domain was a closed interval! So what we have really proven is that the area function
28.3 The Fundamental Theorem
We’ve already seen that these meager axioms hide great power: we could prove that the integral of a bounded function was continuous directly without anything else! But this is only the start of an incredible story. Here, we jump straight to the main event - and prove that these axioms characterize the fundamental theorem of calculus!
Theorem 28.2 (The Fundamental Theorem of Calculus) Let
Proof. Because
Choose an arbitrary
It will be convenient to separate this argument into two cases, depending on if
Thus the real quantity of interest is this integral over
By subdivison (Axiom III), we know that
Dividing through by
and subtracting
We arrive at the inequality
But the numerator here is none other than
Exercise 28.2 Write out the case for
This tells us that the area function of
Corollary 28.1 Let
This connection of integration with antidifferentiation and the classification of antiderivatives has a useful corollary for computation, which is often called the second fundamental theorem
Theorem 28.3 (FTC Part II) Let
Proof. Denote the area function for
Now, let
Where the last equality comes from the fact that
We are going to have a lot of endpoint-subtraction going on, so its nice to have a notation for it.
Definition 28.2 Let
Remark 28.4. It is often convenient when doing calculations to introduce a slight generalization of the integral, which depends on an oriented interval. A natural notation for this is already in use in calculus, using the top and bottom of the integral sign for the locations of the ‘ending’ and ‘starting’ bound respectively:
Show that using this notation, we have a clean generalized subdivision rule: for **all points
This notation helps shorten the computations in the proof of the fundamental theorem (at the expense of adding one new thing to remember).
The fundamental theorem of calculus is a beautiful result for many different reasons. One of course, is that it forges a deep connection between the theory of areas and the theory of derivatives - something missed by the ancients and left undiscovered until the modern advent of the calculus. But second, it shows how incredibly constraining our simple axioms are: we did not prove the fundamental theorem of calculus for any particular definition of the integral (Riemann’s, Lebesgue’s, Darboux’s, etc) but rather showed that if continuous functions are integrable then your theory of integration has no choice whatsoever on how to integrate them!
We’ve seen above that it is possible to construct explicit models of the integration axioms by artificially limiting the domain of integrable functions (to constants, or linear functions for instance). But even these are constrained by the Fundamental theorem: since our example functions were continuous, there was really no choice at all!
The remaining question is of course, is there a theory of integration where all continuous functions are integrable? We will call any definition of integration interesting if it is general enough to include all continuous maps.
Definition 28.3 An integral
28.3.1 Application: Integration Techniques
Given the fundamental theorem holds for continuous functions, its immediate to build up a strong theory of integration
Theorem 28.4 Let
Proof. Because
By the Fundamental Theorem, we can evaluate this by antidifferentiation: let
Using this antiderivative yields
A crucial but seemingly simple observation is to note this is the same value one would get by evaluating the function
And as
Similarly without any further theory we can construct the other main integration technique of the calculus: integration by parts!
Theorem 28.5 Let
Exercise 28.3 Prove this using a similar strategy as to what we did above, but using the product rule instead of the chain rule as a starting point.
28.4 The Work to Come
Its pretty incredible that even though we did not set out to uniquely define the integral via our axioms, they manage to completely determine the integral for any function
A natural and important question then is which continuous functions are integrable? (Or, in our terminology above, is there an interesting integral at all?). As soon as we know
28.4.1 Failure of the ‘Calculus Integral’
The example below shows this is actually a difficult problem to answer: one might try to define the integral using a right endpoint Riemann sum (as one would in a calculus course): from this definition one can prove that all continuous functions are integrable, but then when one goes to try and verify the axioms, one finds this is actually not an integral at all!
Definition 28.4 (The “Calculus Integral”) Let
Such a function
It turns out that while this definition seems unproblematic when applied to elementary functions seen in a calculus course, it has some rather surprising behavior in general: and taking it as our definition would destroy some of the familiar pillars of integration theory!
To find the trouble, we need to look away from the well behaved functions, and investigate the integrability of some monsters. Here we’ll look at the characteristic function of the rationals.
Example 28.3 Let
In fact, its worse than this! As a natural extension of the above, one can show the following:
Exercise 28.4 The function
- The length of the interval, when both endpoints are rational.
- Zero, when one endpoint is rational and the other irrational
This has a very important consequence to our theory: our proposed definition of the integral violates the subdivision rule.
Exercise 28.5 The subdivison rule
Hint: look at the interval